Correlates of Narrow Bracketing

Date01 October 2019
DOIhttp://doi.org/10.1111/sjoe.12311
Published date01 October 2019
Scand. J. of Economics 121(4), 1441–1472, 2019
DOI: 10.1111/sjoe.12311
Correlates of Narrow Bracketing*
Alexander K. Koch
Aarhus University,DK-8210 Aarhus V, Denmark
akoch@econ.au.dk
Julia Nafziger
Aarhus University,DK-8210 Aarhus V, Denmark
jnafziger@econ.au.dk
Abstract
Behavior often deviatesfrom standard predictions because individuals evaluate the consequences
of choices separately (i.e., narrow bracketing) rather than jointly. The main existing theories
classify different narrow bracketing phenomena as either (i) choice errors caused by cognitive
limitations,or (ii) strategies to achieve self-control. Using an online experiment, we find consistent
evidence for theory (ii): mental budgets and narrow goals are related to each other and to
measures of self-control, but are distinct from other forms of narrow bracketing. Evidence for
the complementary theory (i) is less consistent: few choice bracketing phenomena are related to
each other and to cognitive skills.
Keywords: Cognitive skills; mental accounting; narrow bracketing; risky choices; self-control
JEL classification:C91; D03; D81; D91
I. Introduction
It is a puzzle why people often evaluate consequences of choices separately
(i.e., narrow bracketing) rather than jointly (i.e., broad bracketing). Two
main, complementary explanations exist.
On the one hand, certain phenomena of narrow bracketing are
considered to be a choice error (Rabin and Weizs¨acker, 2009), explained by
cognitive limitations or cognitive inertia (Read et al., 1999). For example,
expected utility theory predicts that individuals are approximately risk
neutral for small stakes (Arrow, 1971). Yet, many people would reject
a favorable gamble with equal odds of winning $200 or losing $100 –
*We are grateful to Augenblick et al. (2015) for sharing their do-file, and we thank Kfir
Eliaz for helpful comments. Annette Mortensen, Thomas Stephansen, Mathias Barløse, Katrine
Poulsgaard,and Heidi Christina Thysen provided excellent research assistance. Financialsuppor t
from Aarhus Universitets Forskningsfond, AU IDEAS 2011, Grant number AUFF-E-201-FLS-
1-17, and the Danish Council for Independent Research – Social Sciences, FSE under grant
12-124835, is gratefully acknowledged.
C
The editors of The Scandinavian Journal of Economics 2018.
1442 Correlates of narrow bracketing
suggesting implausibly high levels of risk aversion under expected utility
theory (Rabin, 2000). Narrow bracketing in conjunction with loss aversion
can explain this result. Loss-averse individuals suffer more from losing $100
than they gain from winning $200. Yet, the impact of loss aversion would be
attenuated if the individuals broadly bracketed the lottery with other risks
and wealth they face (Benartzi and Thaler, 1995). To see this, consider two
repetitions of the gain $200 or lose $100 gamble. If an individual aggregates
(broadly brackets) the outcomes of the gambles, then integrating a possible
loss of $100 in one gamble with a gain of $200 in the other gamble implies
that most outcomes of the aggregated gamble (three out of four) are in the
gain domain. Thus, loss aversion has little impact and the individual would
accept the aggregated gambles. In contrast, not integrating the two gambles
would lead to a rejection of each gamble, which can be considered an
error.
On the other hand, in some domains, narrow bracketing appears to be
beneficial. People bracket decisions narrowly to achieve self-control – a
phenomenon termed “motivational bracketing” (e.g., Shefrin and Thaler,
1988; Fudenberg and Levine, 2006; Koch and Nafziger, 2016). For example,
individuals who can choose their working hours, such as taxi drivers, often
appear to have narrow, daily income targets (Camerer et al., 1997). At
first glance, it seems suboptimal for taxi drivers to stop driving when
reaching their daily income target. They could earn more by working
longer when hourly earnings are high, and working fewer hours when they
are low. The reason that taxi drivers set narrow, daily income targets is
that these help to mitigate self-control problems, as Camerer et al. (1997)
conjecture.
The aim of this paper is to examine whether different phenomena
of narrow bracketing correlate with each other and with individual
characteristics, such as cognitive skills and self-control, as predicted by
the complementary theories that classify particular narrow bracketing
phenomena as a choice error (choice bracketing) or as a response to self-
control problems (motivational bracketing). Further, on a more exploratory
level, the correlations help to shed light on the question of whether choice
bracketing and motivational bracketing are distinct phenomena or whether
different bracketing phenomena can be captured by one parsimonious
model of narrow bracketing. For example, narrow bracketing can be seen
as a feature of the prospect theory of Kahneman and Tversky (1979).
It tightly links phenomena of narrow bracketing to reference-dependent
preferences and loss aversion, because the reference point against which
gains and losses are evaluated is often tied to a single, specific decision.
That is, the individual is assumed to bracket this decision narrowly
(e.g., Thaler, 1999).
C
The editors of The Scandinavian Journal of Economics 2018.
A. K. Koch and J. Nafziger 1443
We conduct an online survey experiment among university entrants at
Aarhus University. The survey includes questions and incentivized tasks
related to choice bracketing and motivational bracketing, as well as several
individual characteristics. We hypothesize (i) that the choice bracketing
phenomena are related to each other and to measures of cognitive skills,
and (ii) that the motivational bracketing phenomena are related to each
other and to measures of self-control.
We collect several measures related to choice bracketing, as follows.
Endowment Integration reveals the extent to which subjects integrate
their endowments when making risky choices. The remaining measures
capture phenomena where narrow bracketing goes hand-in-hand with
reference-dependent preferences that can be described by a value function
with three main features (Kahneman and Tversky, 1979): loss aversion,
s-shape, and a reference point.
Insurance counts how many categories of small-scale insurance (such
as insuring a laptop against theft and damage, or buying travel insurance)
a subject reports to have purchased. Paying a high insurance premium to
avoid such small risks is inconsistent with expected utility, but can be
explained by narrow bracketing in conjunction with loss aversion (Rabin
and Thaler, 2001).
Lottery Isolation builds on an incentivized version of a question by
Tversky and Kahneman (1981) that is designed to detect whether people
integrate multiple lotteries or view them in isolation. The question presents
two concurrent lotteries: one has outcomes in the gain domain and the
other has outcomes in the loss domain. A narrow bracketer with reference-
dependent preferences tends to make a risk-averse choice in the gain lottery
and a risk-seeking choice in the loss lottery – choices that are dominated
when considering the broadly bracketed compound lottery (Rabin and
Weizs¨acker, 2009).
Topical Account builds on two questions by Kahneman and Tversky
(1984) that reveal whether a subject narrowly brackets costs and benefits
associated with a particular consumption decision. Specifically, a narrow
bracketer will evaluate the loss of an already purchased theatre ticket
differently from losing an amount of money of equal value.
The variables Loss Aversion and S-Shaped relate to parameters of the
value function that we elicit with price lists. We predict a correlation with
the other choice bracketing phenomena not only because of the theoretical
link between reference-dependent preferences and narrow bracketing, but
also because of the elicitation procedure for the value function. One
can only observe reference-dependent preferences from choice lists if
individuals bracket the choices presented to them narrowly. Loss aversion,
for example, would play no role for decisions if individuals integrated the
experimental risk with their experimental endowment.
C
The editors of The Scandinavian Journal of Economics 2018.

To continue reading

Request your trial

VLEX uses login cookies to provide you with a better browsing experience. If you click on 'Accept' or continue browsing this site we consider that you accept our cookie policy. ACCEPT